President Obama’s Bizarre “Science Czar”: Dr. John P. Holdren, Professional Alarmist

President Obama’s top science advisor and I have something in common: We both have a long-term association with Paul Ehrlich, my former colleague at Stanford University. There any similarity ends, however. Holdren, who has co-authored hooks on population control with Ehrlich and his wife, is the Stanford professors ideological clone. For my part, I have long opposed the prescriptions of the infamous population bombster, and now find myself compelled to reject the almost identical views of the lesser-known but now more powerful Holdren as well.

What views? Let’s start with his 1973 book, co-authored with the Ehrlichs, called Human Ecology: Problems and Solutions. In it, he argued:

“Human values and institutions have set mankind on a collision course with the laws of nature. Human beings cling jealously to their prerogative to reproduce as they please — and they please to make each new generation larger than the last — yet endless multiplication on a finite planet is impossible. Most humans aspire to greater material prosperity, but the number of people that can be supported on Earth if everyone is rich is even smaller than if everyone is poor.”

Their solution, if you can believe it, was to make everyone poor. They argued that the West should be “de-developed,” by which they meant that countries like the U.S. should have their economies deliberately dismantled and their wealth redistributed to the poor at home and abroad.

But their big push was for population control. The publication of the book predated the Roe v. Wade decision, and the authors strongly argued for legalizing abortion as a population control measure. They suggest that abortion cannot really be considered the taking of a human life, on the grounds that neither the fetus, nor the newborn, nor the toddler, is truly human anyway: “The fetus, given the opportunity to develop properly before birth, and given the essential early socializing experiences and sufficient nourishing food during the crucial early years after birth, will ultimately develop into a human being,”1 write the authors. Move over, Peter Singer.

Holdren apparently agrees with the Princeton University “ethicist” that infants up to the age of two or so are not really human beings, and so can be eliminated without qualms.

Holdren and company go so far as to argue that abortion is essentially an act of mercy for “unwanted children” because it spares them from “undesirable consequences,” such as illegitimacy, or growing up in a broken home, or being deemed unfit for military service, They conclude, drawing upon a study from Sweden, that “There seems little doubt that the forced bearing of unwanted children has undesirable consequences not only for the children themselves and their families but for society as well, apart from the problems of overpopulation.”

But who is Holdren to say, on the basis of a single study, that the illegitimate would be better off if they had never been born? What consequence could possibly be more “undesirable” for a child than being deprived of the right to life itself? Better off? They would be dead.

Holdren then attacks opponents of abortion for condemning future generations to an “overcrowded planet.” “Those who oppose abortion often raise the argument that a decision is being made for an unborn person who ‘has no say’. But unthinking actions of the very same people help to commit future unheard generations to misery and early death on an overcrowded planet.” The trouble with this formulation, in which Holdren poses as the defender of generations as yet unborn, is that human beings have been leading longer, healthier lives precisely because our numbers have been growing. Contra Holdren, the prosperity generated by our numbers is helping to stamp out misery and lower mortality rates.

Convinced that mankind faced a population apocalypse, Holdren went on to propose even more extreme measures in his next book, also co-authored with the Ehrlichs. Called Ecoscience, this 1977 book endorsed compulsory abortion, mass sterilization, child abduction, the sterilization and abortion of undesirables, and a “Planetary Regime” with the power to dictate life and death to Americans. I am not making this up, as you will see below.

You might think that no one in their right mind would suggest that American women, like their Chinese counterparts, could be forced to abort their children. Yet Holdren et al. wrote “[I]t has been concluded that compulsory population control laws, even including laws requiring compulsory abortion, could be sustained under the existing Constitution if the population crisis became sufficiently severe to endanger the society” (p. 837). Lest you be fooled by the passive voice (“it has been concluded”), let me point out that it was Holdren and the Ehrlichs themselves, who have not one whit of legal training among them, who “concluded” that there was nothing in the Constitution that forbade forced abortion.

Holdren turns out to have a particular animus against single mothers, whom he apparently believes should have their babies seized by the government and given away to other couples to raise. As he writes on page 786, “One way to carry out this disapproval [of single motherhood] might be to insist that all illegitimate babies he put up for adoption — especially those born to minors, who generally are not capable of caring properly for a child alone. If a single mother really wished to keep her baby, she might be obliged to go through adoption proceedings and demonstrate her ability to support and care for it. Adoption proceedings probably should remain more difficult for single people than for married couples, in recognition of the relative difficulty of raising children alone. It would even be possible to require pregnant single women to marry or have abortions, perhaps as an alternative to placement for adoption, depending on the society.”

The Chinese government’s solution to illegitimacy is to force all pregnant single women to have abortions. Holdren’s scheme is only slightly less draconian; he would give pregnant single women the “choice” of either a shotgun wedding — with the government holding the shotgun — or an abortion. Those who have already given birth would have their babies seized and given away. The fact that these proposals are written in a neutral “scientific” tone does not make them any less appalling. In fact, I find them all the more appalling for the veneer of “scientific” neutrality in which they are cloaked. Hitler’s “Final Solution” for the Jews was written in equally “scientific” language.

Then there is Holdren’s proposal to put infertility drugs into the nation’s drinking water to effect a mass sterilization. “Adding a sterilant to drinking water or staple foods is a suggestion that seems to horrify people more than most proposals for involuntary fertility control,” he writes. But it doesn’t horrify Holdren, who apparently sees no ethical or moral problems with such a nightmarish scheme. Instead, he dispassionately outlines the technical specifications for such a sterilizing agent, which “must be uniformly effective, despite widely varying doses received by individuals, and despite varying degrees of fertility and sensitivity among individuals; it must be free of dangerous or unpleasant side effects; and it must have no effect on members of the opposite sex, children, old people, pets, or livestock” (p. 787–8). Only a morally unhinged individual would imagine a sterilant that the government could use to stop all Americans from having children.

Perhaps because he despaired of ever developing such a mass sterilant, Holdren went on to propose that the government could control women’s reproduction by either sterilizing them outright, or forcing them to accept long-term birth control. In a section called, “Involuntary Fertility Control,” he wrote that “a Program of sterilizing women after their second or third children, despite the relatively greater difficulty of the operation than vasectomy, might be easier to implement than trying to sterilize men … The development of a long-term sterilizing capsule that could be implanted under the skin and removed when pregnancy is desired opens additional possibilities for coercive fertility control. The capsule could be implanted at puberty and might be removable, with official permission, for a limited number of births” (p. 786–7). Here again there are echoes of China’s birth control policy, since women in China must have official permission to get pregnant, and are limited to one child in the cities and two children in the countryside, And, as he suspected, the Chinese government has found it easier to sterilize women than men after they have had their allotted number of children. Men, after all, tend to fight back. But even China, as despotic as its one-child policy is, hasn’t gone as far as Holdren, who imagines a society in which the government chemically sterilizes all girls at puberty.

You might think it cannot get worse. You would be wrong. In Holdren’s imagined population control utopia, anyone whom the government decides is causing “social deterioration,” can be compelled not to have children. Let me quote what I believe is the most chilling sentence in the whole book: “If some individuals contribute to general social deterioration by overproducing children, and if the need is compelling, they can be required by law to exercise reproductive responsibility — just as they can be required to exercise responsibility in their resource-consumption patterns — providing they are not denied equal protection” (p. 838).

There are two ways to read this sentence, both of which are equally repugnant. Here may lurk the old eugenics goal of more children from the fit and fewer from the unfit — with government bureaucrats determining who is contributing to “social deterioration” and who is not. Those who are found to be unfit will he hustled off to the sterilization or abortion clinic to prevent them from reproducing their kind.

But it is also possible that Holdren meant that those who are “overproducing children” are causing social deterioration and that such reckless reproduction must be stopped. In this interpretation, the government must intervene to prevent those who have more than two children, such as believing Christians, homeschoolers, or farm families, from having more children. Does he envision the police arresting women for the crime of being pregnant, bustling them off to clinics for a forced abortion, then sterilizing them to prevent a re-occurrence? That is what routinely happens in China, after all, where the government shares Holdren’s belief that too many people cause “social deterioration.”

Perhaps because Holdren understands that most Americans would object to his population control program, he wants to take matters out of our hands by setting up a world government to oversee it. In a section called, “Toward a Planetary Regime, “he writes that “Perhaps these agencies, combined with the [United Nations Environment Programme] and the United Nations population agencies, might eventually be developed into a Planetary Regime-sort of an international superagency for population, resources, and environment. Such a comprehensive Planetary Regime could control… all natural resources,…all international trade, … including all food on the international market. The Planetary Regime might be given responsibility for determining the optimum population for the world and for each region and for arbitrating each country’s share within the regional limits. Control of population size might remain the responsibility of each government, but the Regime should have some power to enforce the agreed limits” (p, 942–3).

Having lived in the People’s Republic of China (PRC), I can tell you that any government that controls all goods, all food, and all commerce will be a brutal tyranny. This is especially true if — like the PRC and the “Planetary Regime” — it is dedicated to enforcing inhumane forced abortion and mass sterilization laws.

Holdren justifies his proposals — proposals that if enacted would effectively brutalize the entire human population in the name of stopping a global overpopulation catastrophe. “Humanity cannot afford to muddle through the rest of the twentieth century,” he writes breathlessly. “This may be the last opportunity to choose our own and our descendants’ destiny” (p. 944). Yet the eco-catastrophe that he predicted by the year 2000 did not materialize. Instead, as our numbers have grown, so has our prosperity and well being. On the whole, mankind is leading longer, healthier lives than ever before.

Holdren has apparently felt little angst over either his failed predictions of a population apocalypse or his outrageous proposals to counter it, either of which should have been sufficient to disqualify him from being named to advise the President on matters of science and technology. But he has shifted ground. As the perceived “crisis” of population growth has faded — thanks in part to the work of PRI — Holdren began promoting alternative energy, and opposing a missile defense for the U.S.

These days he prefers to talk about another supposed catastrophe that has, like overpopulation a few years ago, seized the imagination of trendy, power-hungry technocrats: global warming. Unless we make dramatic changes in the way we live, Holdren now tells us, we are headed for a climate catastrophe. In a report to the U.N., Holdren predicts a dire future caused by global warming and calls for a global tax on greenhouse gas emissions. Sea levels could rise as much as 1.3 feet by the year 2010, he reportedly said in 2006, a prediction that is waved off by respectable scientists. Same rhetoric, different subject.

Holden, who was trained in Plasma Physics at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, has a long history of opining on subjects to which he brings no particular expertise. He wrote on population issues but was not a demographer, He addresses on energy resources but is not a geophysicist. He issues oracular statements on climate change but is not a climatologist.

What Obama’s new Science Czar really is, is a professional doomsayer along the lines of his mentor, Paul Ehrlich. He has prophesied one end-of-the-world scenario after another to advance his scientific career. He has been, one must admit, rather spectacularly successful at this, and now has the ear of the U.S. President. But he has been consistently wrong on the facts. And the fear mongering that he habitually engages in gives science, and scientists, a bad name.

Endnotes

1 Paul R. Ehrlich, Anne H. Ehrlich and John P. Holdren, Human Ecology: Problems and Solutions (W.H. Freeman and Company, 1973), p. 235. The specific passage expressing the author’s view that a baby “will ultimately develop into a human being” is chapter 8, which is titled “Population Limitation.”

Never miss an update!

Get our Weekly Briefing! We send out a well-researched, in-depth article on a variety of topics once a week, to large and growing English-speaking and Spanish-speaking audiences.

Subscribe to our Weekly Briefing!

Receive expert analysis every Tuesday morning.
This field is for validation purposes and should be left unchanged.